The Value of Civilian Arms Possession As Deterrent To Crime Or Defense
Against Crime
This article is copyrighted. It was provided by the author, Don B. Kates,
Jr., and is distributed with the permission of the author. It can be uploaded to
other BBSs as long as it is not altered, and it may be cited as long as credit
is given. As per Don Kates' note:
"If you publish this, you must indicate that it is the text and footnotes
to an article that appeared in v. 18 of the AMERICAN J. OF CRIM. LAW
(1991)." So noted.
The Value of Civilian Arms Possession As Deterrent To Crime Or Defense
Against Crime
By Don B. Kates Jr.*
* LL. B. Yale University (1966). Member of the California, District of
Columbia, Missouri and United States Supreme Court Bars. San Francisco partner,
Benenson & Kates; of counsel, Hallisey & Johnson, San Francisco, Ca. I
wish to thank the following for their assistance: Professors David Bordua
(Sociology, U. of Illinois), Philip J. Cook (Public Policy Studies and
Economics, Duke U.), F. Smith Fussner (History, Emeritus, Reed College), Gary
Green (Criminology, U. of Evansville),
Ted Robert Gurr (Political Science, U. of Colorado), John Kaplan (Law
Stanford U.), Raymond Kessler (Criminal Justice, Memphis State U.), Gary Kleck
(Criminology, Florida State U.), Daniel Polsby (Law, Northwestern U.) James D.
Wright (Social and Demographic Research Institute, U. of Mass., Amherst); Ms. P.
Kates and C. Montagu, San Francisco, Ca. and Ms. S. Byrd and Mr. C. Spector,
Berkeley, Ca. Of course for errors either of fact or interpretation the
responsibility is mine alone.
Introduction
The crime reductive value of civilian firearms ownership is a central issue
in the "gun control" controversy. Sixty five years of vitriolic debate have
amply proven the wisdom of a leading early 20th Century opponent of gun
ownership, New York City Chief Magistrate William McAdoo in predicting that
- We shall make no progress in removing this national menace until this
basic fact as to the ineffectiveness of arming citizens is well and thoroughly
understood by the people who foolishly buy pistols and arm themselves. [1]
The gun owner's almost talismanic faith in the protective efficacy of guns
leads him to cling to them notwithstanding the indubitable evils to which guns
all too often lend themselves. The other side seeks to outlaw handguns (many
would prefer outlawing all guns), dogmatically convinced not just that, on
balance, guns do more harm than good, but that "In the hands of the general
public handguns confer virtually no social benefit" [2]; and, since legislatures
have proved unwilling to ban handguns, Magistrate McAdoo's intellectual
descendants urge the courts to do so, in effect, by imposing strict liability
for the manufacture, distribution or ownership of a gun. [2A]
Given the fervor of each side in this decades-old debate, it is not
surprising that neither has seemed fazed by the lack, until comparatively
recently, of any substantial quantum of hard evidence upon which to base
rational judgments about the supposed utility of civilian firearms ownership in
reducing crime. The purpose of this paper is to analyze the empirical evidence
on that issue most of which has become available only in the last decade. [3]
Prior to such discussion it is necessary, however, to set out some caveats and
two definitions.
Caveats
Obviously the conclusions reached in this paper may have import for the gun
control debate; indeed in the case of at least one oft- mentioned option they
seem decisive. [3A] But this paper emphatically does not attempt to resolve the
general issue of the extent to which public policy should circumscribe or allow
gun ownership. To resolve that would require broadly assessing at least the
following: (1) not just any crime reductive utility, but every other supposed
benefit of gun ownership to individuals or society generally (e.g. conservation
and ecology, promotion of national defense, deterring despotism etc., etc.); (2)
comparison to those alleged benefits of all the costs (e.g. accidents, violence
and suicide) of gun ownership -- in light of a hardheaded evaluation of (3) the
likely extent to which non-compliance or other factors might frustrate the
salutory purposes of a gun ban, (4) the costs to the criminal justice system of
trying to overcome such non-compliance, and (5) constitutional barriers either
to particular gun restrictions or to the means needed for their enforcement.
[4]
In other words to determine what particular level of gun control is desirable
requires an enormously broader inquiry than is attempted here. As the factors
just enumerated suggest, it requires a pragmatic inquiry: not just a balancing
whether in the abstract of whether guns do more harm than good but consideration
of whether, in fact, any particular control strategy will produce a favorable
trade-off by actually reducing the harms (or the more important ones) that
involve guns more than it reduces the values. [5] Such an inquiry requires
systematic attention to all the foregoing factors and to numerous subsidiary
issues, e.g. could the supposed benefits conferred by civilian gun ownership be
better achieved by non-lethal means? [6] In contrast this paper is limited to
only one sub-issue of #(1) of the factors enumerated in the last paragraph.
My second caveat is that the disproportionate attention given herein to
studies and analyses authored by opponents of gun ownership reflects necessity
rather than a bias against gun ownership. The fact is that the gun lobby has, in
effect, defaulted as to the production of academic literature. [6A] Thus studies
by "gun control" advocates constituted almost the whole corpus of academic
literature available on gun issues until the last decade when more neutral
scholars began addressing those issues. Significant of all too many aspects of
the gun control controversy is that gun owners require no scholarship -- nor
even "sagecraft" -- to maintain their talismanic faith in the protective
efficacy of guns, although they have produced a voluminous technical literature
on defensive weapons and tactics. [7]
Definitions
The first definitional problem was to find apt shorthand labels for the
respective positions of the gun lobby and its opponents. In line with the
imagery of religious faith this article employs, the terms gun iconodule and gun
iconoclast seemed appropriate. But the difficulties inhering in terms of
reference relating to a now-obscure Byzantine religious controversy are obvious.
So instead the terms "pro- gun" and "anti-gun" will be used herein for the
respective polar extremes in the American gun controversy.
It bears emphasis that these "pro-gun" and "anti-gun" positions are extremes
-- albeit they have, tragically in my view, tended to dominate and drown out
more moderate voices. In fact, polls over the past half century consistently
show that most Americans, including a majority of gun owners, are neither
pro-gun nor anti-gun but rather "pro-control". [7A] On the one hand, most
Americans reject anti-gun disdain for self-defense and the basic anti-gun creed
of the inherent depravity of guns. On the other hand, most Americans also reject
the puerile pro-gun shibboleth that the existence of laws against murder and
other violent crime makes it superfluous to reinforce them with sensible,
profilactic controls on weapons that can be used to commit such crime. This
article may be described as a self-conscious attempt to apply the moderate
pro-control position which characterizes the rational majority to the claims
which each extreme offers about the crime reductive value of civilian gun
ownership.
The second definitional problem involves distinguishing actual use of a gun
to thwart a crime in progress (hereinafter described as defense-use) from the
deterrent effect of actual or perceived victim arms possession in dissuading
criminals from attempting a crime at all (hereinafter described as deterrence).
Though basic, this distinction has only rarely been observed even by
criminologists and anti-gun writers and almost never by pro-gun writers. It is
crucial because conceptual and practical difficulties make the evidence for
deterrence more complex and more ambiguous than for defense-use.
The order in which this article treats these issues is first defense-use and
then the possible deterrent effects of civilian gun ownership. But before either
aspect of defensive gun ownership can be analyzed empirically certain ethical or
cultural concerns must be addressed -- if only because they have so often
intruded into, and more or less subtly obfuscated, purportedly empirical
discussions of these issues.
NON-EMPIRICAL (MORAL AND PHILISOPHICAL) CONSIDERATIONS
Some analysts see in the notoriously extreme bitterness of the gun control
debate a clash of cultural and ethical values disguised in more or less
pseudo-criminological terms. The proposition is not that criminological
disagreement is not a part of "the Great American Gun War" but that such
disagreement is minor in comparison to the violent cultural and moral antagonism
it cloaks. [8] Indicative of the depth of those antagonisms is the description
offered in the encyclopedic review of American gun control literature done by
the University of Massachusetts for the National Institute of Justice): that
many gun control advocates seriously view gun owners as "demented and blood-
thirsty psychopaths whose concept of fun is to rain death on innocent creatures,
both human and otherwise" [8A]; that gun ownership is "simply beastly behavior"
the gun being both real and symbolic mechanism of a peculiar savagery lurking in
an American soul that is "hard, isolate, stoic and a killer". [9] As one would
expect, the pro- gun is utterly different; as Col. Jeff Cooper, one of the more
articulate spokesmen for defense gun ownership, puts it:
- Weapons compound man's power to achieve; they amplify the capabilities of
both the good man and the bad, and to exactly the same degree, having no will
of their own. Thus, we must regard them as servants, not masters -- and good
servants to good men. Without them, man is diminished, and his opportunities
to fulfill his destiny are lessened. An unarmed man can only flee from evil,
and evil is not overcome by fleeing from it. [10]
It might be argued that there can be no basis for rationally evaluating these
violently contradictory points of view, at least insofar as they constitute
professions of cultural, moral or quasi- religious premises. But even
fundamental premises are not necessarily immune from rational evaluation. A
doubtless apocryphal tale holds that when James Joyce publicly repudiated his
Catholicism he was approached by an English reporter who asked him if he would
now become a Protestant. "Just because I've lost my faith", Joyce is said to
have replied, "do you think I've lost my reason as well?" The point is that it
is sometimes or to some extent possible to determine whether professions of
moral faith are founded in reason. Thus, for instance, the anti-gun response to
Cooper's profession of faith is: that a guns is simply not an effective defense
to criminal attack; that to flee if possible, and otherwise to submit,
constitutes the only viable form of opposition to robbery, rape etc. [10A]
Whether this is so will be explored infra. But if it proves to be true, Col.
Cooper's faith that guns allow resistance to evil is exposed as contrary to
reason.
Examination of Some Non-Empirical Elements of Anti-gun Faith-
Some professions of anti-gun morality may also be subject to refutation
either as contra-factual or as internally inconsistent: A prime instance of
internal inconsistency occurs in connection with statements like those of the
distinguished nationally syndicated columnist and cultural historian Garry Wills
who feels that "gun fetishists" are at once immoral and unpatriotic, "traitors,
enemies of their own patria", "anti-citizens" arming "against their own
neighbors." [11] Yet what Prof. Wills and the many others who echo such
statements contemplate as the appropriate response when people are subjected to
criminal attack is summoning a police officer. [11-1]
There is an amusing, but none the less very real, impediment to analyzing
this position: it is so inconsistent that one who does not start out accepting
it is hard put to believe that Prof. Wills et al are actually saying what they
are, in fact, saying. Thus I emphasize that their concern is not simply
pragmatic, e.g. to deny that gun-armed self-defense is effective or to laud the
obvious advantages of police assistance when that option is open. Entirely
independent of (though often accompanying) such pragmatic concerns, anti-gun
advocates advance the moral view that under no circumstances is it ever
legitimate to use a gun in defense of self or family. [11A] Thus Prof. Wills
holds that people who own guns in order to be able to protect their families in
the event that police assistance proves not immediately available exhibit a
morally abhorrent attitude toward fellow-Americans. [11A] Of course, if
consistently adhered to, Prof. Wills' view is as immune from rational dispute as
is any other moral belief. But if one is willing to call on others (the police)
to defend his family with a gun it is patently inconsistent to condemn the
morality of others because they are willing to defend their families themselves
if the police are unavailable when the need arises.
Another common profession of the anti-gun faith is that which characterizes
defensive gun ownership as "paranoid". [12A] What "paranoid" means in this
context is not entirely clear (at least today). It may now be no more than a
psych-jargon dressed expression of Prof. Wills' abhorrence of defensive gun
ownership. But what "paranoid" literally conveys is a view that was common among
American intellectuals up to about a decade ago. In that view the extent of
crime had been vastly exaggerated as a result of public hysteria; crime was
neither increasing nor dangerous or pervasive enough to justify being armed;
such a precaution so far exceeded the real level of danger as to be an
irrational overreaction. [12B] Thus it may be useful to compare defensive gun
ownership to another kind of precaution that is generally deemed sensible.
Homeowners who buy earthquake insurance are considered not paranoid but prudent
even in California where such insurance runs at least $2.00 per $1,000.00
valuation, or $300.00 annually (for what is a middle class dwelling at
California prices, c. $150,000.00). [12C] Over a ten year period the homeowner
will pay $3,000.00 in earthquake insurance premiums. In contrast, a used Smith
& Wesson .38 special revolver, which will last forever with proper
maintenance, costs perhaps $150.00. Yet the likelihood of an average American
household (much less one in a high crime area) suffering burglary or robbery
over that period is roughly 10 times greater than of injury from all natural
disasters (flood, earthquake, hurricane, tornado) combined [13].
Can defensive gun ownership be deemed an irrational overreation if it is
reasonable to pay 20 times as much to insure against a danger less than one
tenth as likely? The gun owner might even argue that his weapon is a better
investment in that it may actually avert the anticipated harm while insurance
only recoups its costs. It may be objected that insurance is not comparable to a
gun since insurance always pays off, but whether gun ownership protects against
crime is a matter of controversy. True enough, but beside the point which is
"paranoia". If the empirical evidence discussed infra proves the gun owner's
faith in the weapon's protective efficacy to be wrong then wrong is what it is
-- not "paranoid". That gun ownership does not represent so exaggerated a
perception of the crime problem as to constitute irrational overreaction is made
evident by the now well accepted view that crime makes life significantly more
dangerous here than it is in many other countries. [13-1] Moreover, if fear of
crime equates to paranoia, the mental health of gun owners appears actually to
be superior to that of non-owners; apparently because gun owners feel more
confident about their ability to deal with crime, studies find them less
frightened of it than are non-gun owners living in the same areas. [13A]
But whatever the benefits of lessened fear to gun owners, for society in
general what is unquestionably more important is the part guns play -- some
people believe it causative -- in about 33,000 suicides, accidents and murders
annually. [14] Thus regardless of any fear reductive effect, gun ownership may
be contra-indicated, particularly for people in the high-risk groups for gun
abuse [15]. But, as noted earlier, the desirability of a univeral gun ban, or of
any other particular level of restriction, involves issues far beyond the scope
of this article.
The police as a source of personal protection for individual citizens.
Another possible interpretation of the paranoia characterization is that
defensive gun ownership is "paranoid" because personal self defense has been
rendered obsolete by the existence of a professional police force. Regrettably
this exaggerates the factual effects of policing and totally misstates its
function in law and theory, as plaintiffs who attempt to sue for non-protection
have found. [16] Doubtless the deterrent effect of professional policing helps
assure that many will never be so unfortunate as to live in circumstances in
which they will require personal protection. But for those who do need such
protection -- e.g. women threatened by former boyfriends or husbands -- the fact
is that the police do not function as bodyguards for individuals.
Rather the police function is to deter crime in general by patrol activities
and by apprehension after the crime has occured. If circumstances permit, the
police should and will protect a citizen in distress. But they are not legally
duty bound even to do that, nor to provide any direct protection -- no matter
how urgent a distress call they may receive. [16] A fortiori the police have no
responsibility to, and do not, provide personal protection to citizens who have
been threatened (although in major cities police may perform bodyguard services
for the mayor and other prominent officials).
Typical of cases enunciating the non-responsibility of the police for
protecting individual citizens is Warren v District of Columbia [17] in which
three rape victims sued the city and its police department under the following
facts: Two of the victims were upstairs when they heard the other being attacked
by men who had broken in downstairs. Half an hour having passed and their
roommate's screams having ceased, they assumed the police must have arrived in
response to their repeated phone calls. In fact their calls had somehow been
lost in the shuffle while the roommate was being beaten into silent acquiesence.
So when the roommates went downstairs to see to her, as the court's opinion
graphically describes it, "For the next fourteen hours the women were held
captive, raped, robbed, beaten, forced to commit sexual acts upon each other,
and made to submit to the sexual demands" of their attackers. [19]
Having set out these facts, the court promptly exonerated the District of
Columbia and its police, as was clearly required by
- [the] fundamental principle of American law that a government and its
agents are under no general duty to provide public services, such as police
protection, to any individual citizen. [19]
As the phrase "fundamental principle of American law" suggests, this holding
is not some legal aberration unique to the District of Columbia. It is
universal, being enuciated by formal statute as well as judicial decision in
many states. [20] Nor is it simply a cynical ploy for government to avoid just
liability. The proposition that individuals must be responsible for their own
immediate safety, with police providing only an auxiliary general deterrent, is
inherent in a high crime society. Consider the matter just in terms of the
number of New York City women who each year seek police help, reporting threats
by ex-husbands, ex-boyfriends etc.: to bodyguard just those women would exhaust
the resources of the nation's largest police department, leaving no officers
available for street patrol, traffic control, crime detection and apprehension
of perpetrators, responding to emergency calls etc., etc. [21] Given what New
York courts have called "the crushing nature of the burden" [22], the police
cannot be made responsible for protecting the individual citizen. Providing such
protection is up to the individual who is threatened; it is not the function of
the police.
"Vigilantism" and related concepts
In tandem with anti-gun disdain for armed self-defense [22A] the common
misunderstanding that the police exist to protect individuals has given rise to
an elusive, but frequently expressed, attitude that equates gun use in defense
of self or others to "vigilantism". A striking facet of this attitude is that it
not only outweighs but even reverses the approbation normally accorded Good
Samaritans: Thus based on a study of those who rescued crime victims and/or
arrested their attackers, PSYCHOLOGY TODAY disapprovingly characterizes them in
terms of the fact that 81% of these Good Samaritans "own guns and some carry
them in their cars. They are familiar with violence, feel competent to handle
it, and don't believe they will be hurt if they get involved." [22B] Similarly
an anti-gun survey actually classifies gun owners as "violence prone" based on
positive responses not to questions about criminality but about the legitimacy
of using force in order to stop a crime in progress or rescue its helpless
victim. [22C] Similarly the editor of a book on the legal status of Good
Samaritans introduces it with the question
- Are we to encourage the ordinary citizen to take direct action in the
prevention of crime or the apprehension of criminals, after centuries of
social development clearly pointing toward the elimination of vigilante [sic]
action and the concentration of responsibility in the hands of public
officials? [22D]
Implicit in the foregoing quotation is as close to a definition as such
references to vigilantism ever seem to come: though Good Samaritanism is highly
creditable in other contexts, it somehow becomes "vigilante action" if it
involves "the ordinary citizen" in "the prevention of crime or the apprehension
of criminals...." (i.e. defending self or others. As with Garry Wills' views,
[22E] the underlying concept seems to be that the defense of citizens is so
exclusively the job of the police that it is a usurpation for ordinary citizens
to defend themselves or each other. Thus in his critically acclaimed book CRIME
IN AMERICA former Attorney General Ramsey Clark ringingly denounces gun
ownership for self-defense on two (apparently related) grounds: that it is
atavistic and uncivilized, "anarchy, not order under law -- a jungle where each
relies on himself for survival"; and that it both usurps a state prerogative and
ia a reproach to our polity for gun owners arrogate to themselves the right to
defend themselves because: "A state in which a citizen needs a gun to protect
himself from crime has failed to perform its first purpose." [23]
For all its appeal to refined and high-minded (but uncritical) readers, such
an attitude lacks practicality in actual application. How does society benefit
if, instead of shooting the ex-husband who breaks into her house, a woman allows
herself to be killed because the civilized thing to do is to wait for him to be
arrested for her murder? Far from advancing the cause of rational gun control,
such attitudes actually retard it by creating "straw men" which aid the gun
lobby in diverting attention from serious arguments for control. Unfortunately
such extreme anti-gun attitudes have played a part in shaping the ideology and
rhetoric of the gun control movement -- and have particularly influenced its
analyses of defensive gun use. Even supposedly pragmatic works appear subtly
colored by the unstated but unshakable belief that, even when legal, defensive
gun use represents vigilantism or some other social wrong. It will suffice to
present only one example of this subtle coloration here since others will be
discussed infra:
As noted earlier, murderers generally have long prior histories of criminal
and otherwise dangerously aberrant behavior; domestic homicide particularly
- is often not an isolated occurence or outbreak, but rather is the
culminating event in a pattern of interpersonal abuse, hatred and violence
that stretches back well into the histories of the parties involved. [24] The
day-to-day reality is that most family murders are prefaced by a long history
of assaults. [24A]
If the victims of homicidal attack are often related to or acquainted with or
their attackers, it follows that often times when a victim has to kill in self
defense the deceased attacker will have been an acquaintance or relative rather
than some unknown rapist, robber or other intruder. Yet without so stating --or
even mentioning the issue at all -- anti-gun works invariably misclassify such
lawful defensive shootings as murder by lumping them together with real murder
under the misleading rubric acquaintance and domestic homicide. Viz. the almost
identical pseudo-statistical formulations in publications issued by the Handgun
Control Staff of the anti-gun U.S. Conference of Mayors to the effect that "use
of firearms for self-protection is more likely to lead to ... death among family
and friends than to the death of an intruder." [25]
Even in a violent society the number of homicidally irrational aberrants is
so small that few of us have such friends, acquaintances or relatives. But some
people do have that misfortune. Of course it is tragic when, for instance, an
abused woman has to shoot to stop a (current or former) boyfriend or husband
from beating her to death. But it is highly misleading to count such incidents
as costs of gun ownership by misclassifying them with the very thing they
prevent: murder between "family and friends". However atavistic or unpatriotic
such incidents may be, they are not vigilantism and they are not costs; rather
they are palpable benefits of defensive gun ownership from society's and the
victims' point of view if not from their attackers'.
Both Anglo-American and foreign law affirm what Prof. Wechsler called "the
universal judgment that there is no social interest in preserving the lives of
the aggressors at the cost of those of their victims." [26] While medieval
common law looked askance at the social value of what it called homicide se
defendendo, [27] later thinkers from Grotius, Locke, Montesquieu, Beccaria and
the Founding Fathers on through Bishop, Pollock, Brandeis to Perkins and beyond
have deemed self defense unqualifiedly beneficial to society. [28] It is only
the unnecessary or excessive use of force that is harmful and wrong.
Furthermore, that harm is qualitatively the same whether the wrong is commited
by citizens or by the police. Unless "vigilantism" is a solecism it must, on the
one hand, not apply to lawful defensive use of force by anyone, while on the
other hand it must condemn all excessive or unnecessary uses of force for the
purpose of imposing summary punishment, whether the vigilantes be citizens or
police. [28A]
With the issue of vigilantism thus properly understood, concerns over victim
misuse of force can be seen in proper perspective. While qualitatively the evil
of vigilantism is the same whether committed by civilians or police,
quantitatively only police vigilantism is a major social problem today. In
contrast civilian vigilantism appears to be quite rare -- perhaps because
officials are alert to the need for vigor in suppressing it. Civilians' claims
to have used deadly force defensively receive very close examination, with
prosecution likely in the event of wrongdoing. Unfortunately comparable review
is rare when police misuse of deadly force is suspected; several studies suggest
that a high proportion of police homicides are unjustified, [29] yet officers
are rarely prosecuted even for clearly wrongful use of deadly force. [29A] These
findings are buttressed by the extensive evidence adduced in civil rights cases
like Webster v City of Houston [30] in which it was held to be a de facto
municipal policy for each officer to carry an untraceable "drop gun" to be
planted on those he might shoot (in order to falsely validate his later claim of
self defense). It is perhaps also significant that in comparing police to
civilian shootings of alleged criminals the police have been found to be 5.5
times more likely to have shot an innocent person in the belief that he was a
criminal. [31]
This is not to deny that civilian gun misuse is a legitimate subject of
concern. The point is only that current legal sanctions appear generally
sufficient to deter civilian "vigilantism". So the principal problem in this
area is effective oversight of police use of force. The American Civil Liberties
Union's tergiversations about the issue are significant: in 1968 the ACLU
endorsed unspecified "gun controls" on the express ground that this would
safeguard dissenters and the criminally accused from private violence. When the
National Coalition to Ban Handguns was organized, the ACLU gave specific content
to this position by joining. In the early 1980s the ACLU revised its 1968
resolution by deleting the express rationale, with membership in the Coalition
being continued without any express civil liberties rationale. As of mid-1986,
however, the ACLU has withdrawn from the Coalition. In sum, however persuasive
the general public policy reasons for banning guns may be, they are not
compelling as a civil liberties issue. [32]
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE AS TO THE VALUE OF ARMS, A pro-gun analysis
Earlier in this article the disproportionate attention it gives to anti-gun
analyses was attributed to their virtual monopoly of the scholarly literature
(until neutral criminologists began to discuss defensive firearms use in the
last decade). [33] Yet at least pseudo- scientific analyses have sometimes
appeared in material written for gun owners and their sympathizers. One example
is the apparently self- published book MYTHS ABOUT GUNS by James E. Edwards whom
the book's rear jacket decribes as a lawyer and former mayor in Coral Gables,
Fla. In bold red letters the front jacket proclaims: "Theme of the book: More
Guns ... Less Crime". The jacket then proceeds to describe the book's purpose as
to provide
- A concise, indexed, documented, pro-gun book of ready reference which
explodes the main dogmas and myths of the anti-gun fanatics. Useful for
debates, legislative hearings, letters to the editor and fighting bad gun
laws.
Mr. Edwards does energetically pursue that theme, offering three tables and
two graphs (albeit all reflecting the same data base) to prove that "as shown by
official studies firearms ownership and the commission of crime ... gun
ownership by the average citizen does not promote crime but reduces crime."
[33A] Each of these proofs compares the percent of households in the East,
South, Mid-West and West respectively that in a single 1968 survey admitted
owning either a handgun or a gun of any kind to the rates of violent crime,
property crime and all crime respectively in those regions in the years 1968,
1972 and 1976. [33A]
Unfortunately such comparisons stumble on various methodological obstacles,
including: 1) radical changes in regional patterns of gun ownership as indicated
by mid-1970s survey data; [34] 2) that "survey data on the level of national
regions [results in] aggragated units too large and internally heterogenous for
useful analysis"; [35] and 3) the sleight of hand Mr. Edwards uses to massage
the data into suppporting his argument. [36]
But above and beyond these problems is an even more basic error which
deserves extended discussion because of its almost universal appearance when gun
issues of any kind are analyzed by partisans on either side. This lies in two
assumptions whose fatuity ought to be apparent to anyone who has ever had an
introductory course in social science. The first of these assumptions is that a
correlation between two phenomena is sufficient to prove that one of them has
caused the other. This may be illustrated by the fact that Mr. Edwards is quite
right about his "more guns ... less crime" correlation; indeed, it is supported
by far stronger evidence than he himself presents. [37] But by the same token,
there could probably be established an equally strong negative correlation
between more cows ... less crime. Before breaking into a paegn of praise to
Bessie the Great Protector, it might be wise to ask whether this correlation
represents anything beyond a spurious artifact of rurality: cows tend to be
found in rural areas and crime doesn't. Of course the low per capita crime rates
in rural America may be attributable to its high rates of gun ownership. But for
the rational and dispassionate observer more proof of that is required than the
bald correlation between "more guns ... less crime."
Mr. Edwards' second false assumption is that, even where some basis exists
for deducing causation from a correlation between two factors, which is the
cause and which the effect can not be blithely presumed according to one's
preconceived perspective. This may be illustrated by another frequently
encountered, but erroneous, pro-gun argument: that states which severely
restrict handgun ownership have higher crime rates than less restrictive states.
[38] A factual difficulty with this as a proof that gun ownership reduces crime
is that the studies do not consistently show the more restrictive areas have
more crime; some studies show them with no more crime than less gun restrictive
areas. [39] But even if the more restrictive were to be found to have more
crime, other explanations are equally or more plausible than the deterrent or
self- defense effects of gun ownership in reducing crime. Prof. Polsby, refering
to such a finding by a respected scholar who is markedly less convinced of the
value of gun ownership than Mr. Edwards (or Prof. Polsby himself), notes
[39A]:
Thus to evaluate the defensive utility of firearms it is necessary to
consider forms of evidence more directly relevant than mere inference from
comparisons of the crime statistics of different jurisdictions or regions. This
requires turning from pro- to anti-gun authors since they provided the earliest
attempts to analyze more directly relevant forms of evidence. Because the
latters' views will be found even less persuasive under close scrutiny than than
those of the gun lobby it is important to reemphasize the definitions with which
this article began: the term anti-gun is not here used as a synonym for
"pro-control", but in its literal sense of antagonism toward gun ownership. Such
morally or culturally based antagonism (and an associated disdain for the right
of self-defense) underlies much of the argument for banning handguns based on
the purportedly empirical claim that guns are useless for self-defense. But it
simply does not follow from the untenability of those claims that we must accede
to puerile gun lobby arguments against the need for rational control. The fact
that handguns are useful no more exempts them from reasonable regulation than
the fact that automobiles and innumerable other commodities are useful
preccludes reasonable regulation to minimize the likelihood of their being
misused. [39B]
Lawful self defense homicides as an index to defensive gun use -
The standard arguments against the utility of defensive gun ownership date
back to the early part of the Century; even their more modern formulations were
all written at least a decade ago. Because directly relevant empirical evidence
has been largely unavailable until recently, such arguments have tended to be
speculative rather than empirical. For example it was (and is) argued that
resistance is useless and dangerous because criminals are more ruthless or
better shots or will have the drop on victims. [40] Where empirical evidence has
been cited it consists in idiosyncratic local statistics of self defense
homicide suggesting that gun use in self defense is a very uncommon phenomenon.
[41] From this it is argued that reduced gun availability would confer great
benefit at little corresponding cost because "Guns purchased for protection are
rarely used for that purpose." [42]
Anti-gun argumentation from lawful homicide figures provides clearly better
evidence of the extent of defensive gun use than Mr. Edwards', and other pro-gun
attempts to infer it from differentials in crime rates. But lawful homicide
figures as an index to overall defensive gun uses raise problems not only
conceptually [43] but, more important, factually. In the vast majority of
defensive gun uses the outcome is not that criminals die but only: that they are
wounded or injured or that they are apprehended or scared off without being
injured at all. [44] So even had far more broadly based long term,
geographically diverse lawful homicide figures been available before the 1980s,
homicides are too small a proportion of overall defensive gun uses to be a
reliable index to the frequency of such uses. At least if better indexes were
available, one would certainly not measure the value of guns in police work by
simply totting up the number of violent felons police kill. By the same token
lawful defensive homicides are not a fair measure of the overall value of
defense guns to civilians.
The justification for anti-gun use of the idiosyncratic local justifiable
homicide statistics is that until recently those have been the only available
data from which the extent of civilian defensive gun use could even remotely be
inferred. But this still does not excuse the misleading selection and
manipulation of such data. For instance, it is well known (the point having been
made often in anti-gun studies [45]) that householders rarely have the
opportunity to use guns against burglars since burglars take care to strike when
no one is home to shoot them. It was therefore misleading to cite as evidence
that defense guns are rarely used under any circumstances the rarity of
intruders being killed by householders. Concommitantly misleading was the
citation of such statistics without even mentioning [46] the much higher
incidence of lawful defense homicides of other kinds -- e.g. woman kills
homicidal ex-boyfriend, shopkeeper kills robber etc. [46A] By the same token it
was highly misleading to cite "guesstimates" by Detroit, Los Angeles and New
York City police officers of the number of criminals civilians were killing
there in the mid-1960s without mentioning the availability from the Chicago
Police Department of complete and official figure showing that for decades the
numbers of lawful defensive homicides by civilians had generally equalled the
numbers by police and lately were tending to outnumber them by as much as 3-1.
[47]
The effect of these and other statistical manipulations was to artificially
minimize the incidence of lawful defensive homicides (and therefore of overall
defensive gun use inferrable therefrom) in the anti-gun studies. Consider the
now-discredited -- though still widely cited -- comparison that handgun
accidents kill 6 times as many householders as householders kill burglars [48].
Based on this finding of an anti-gun study of Cleveland gun deaths, it might be
thought that gun accidents must account for a substantial part of the yearly
handgun death toll; yet even nationwide the National Safety Council can identify
only about 300 accidental handgun fatalities annually -- as compared to c. 6,000
handgun suicides and 6,000-9,500 handgun murders. [49] The actual ratio of fatal
handgun accidents to lawful defensive killings is not six to one in favor of the
former but more like 1 to 3 in favor of the latter. [50] While something unique
about Cleveland might explain this 1800% deviation from the norm, a more
plausible suggestion that has been made is that the number of accidents in
Cleveland was inflated by the random inclusion through misclassification of
large numbers of what were actually handgun suicides. [51] In sum, the anti-gun
attempts to minimize the extent of defensive gun use could not have been
sustained by full and accurate description of even the sparse city-level lawful
homicide data available when the various anti-gun studies were written. [54]
Subsequently as such data have become available for other cities, and on
state and national bases, the anti-gun argument has suffered further. [55]
Though it does not publish them in its yearly Uniform Crime Reports, the FBI now
collects national "justifiable homicide" figures which show armed citizens
annually lawfully kill more violent felons than do the police. [55] Yet even
these figures actually underrepresent the full extent of lawful defensive
homicide by 50% or more. The FBI statistics count as criminal any intentional
killing whose legality was initially questioned (even those later ruled lawful
by the district attorney, coroner's jury etc.). [56] Also, based on the obsolete
distinction between "excusable" and "justifiable" homicide, the FBI excludes
from the latter category any killing that occured in defense of the defender's
life rather than in repelling a felony having some other object. In other words,
however strange it may seem: if a woman shoots an ex-boyfriend who is strangling
her, or a contract killer hired by her husband who wants to inherit her estate,
the FBI counts that as a criminal homicide (for statistical purposes only)
because the attacker's immediate purpose was only to kill her; but if a merchant
kills a robber or a woman kills a rapist the FBI counts that as a justifiable
homicide because the attacker's purpose was some crime other than homicide.
[56A] It is estimated that if all lawful civilian self defense killings were
counted, the actual number of violent criminals killed by citizens might exceed
the number killed by police each year by as much as five times. [57]
Survey data as an index to defensive gun use
Until fairly recently survey evidence on gun issues was limited to the
results of whatever general unfocussed inquiries the Gallup or Harris polls had
haphazardly decided to ask in the 4 or 5 question polls they had devoted to gun
matters over the years. But during the past decade both pro- and anti-gun groups
have sponsored intensive sophisticated multi-question private national surveys
on various issues in the gun control debate. Common to several of these private
surveys were questions as to whether guns in the respondents' homes had been
used defensively. The surveys were not conducted directly by the partisan groups
sponsoring them but by independent private polls including Peter Hart and
Patrick Caddell (for the anti-gun groups) and the Decision Making Information
organization (for the NRA).[57A] Although less well known than Gallup or Harris,
these are respected polls: the Hart and Caddell firms regularly poll for
Democratic Party groups and candidates (President Carter and Senator Cranston
among them), while the Republican luminaries DMI has worked for include
Presidents Ford and Reagan.
As with any poll, these are subject to the objection that they generalize
about a population of upwards of 250 million on the basis of information
obtained from a sample of only about 1,500 supposedly representative people.
[58] But, excepting objections to surveys in general, there is no reason for
discounting the results of these gun polls in particular; while these polls were
paid for by partisans, the reputations of the independent organizations actually
conducting them precludes any question of falsification and academic studies
have favorably cited and relied upon their results. [59] To exclude even
unreasonable doubts as to validity, however, the discussion here will be based
only on the evidence of anti-gun-sponsored polling. It is possible to simply
discard the results of the NRA-sponsored polls since the data yields on
defensive gun use from all the surveys are mutually consistent. [60] Based only
on the survey evidence sponsored by anti- gun groups, it has been calculated
that handguns are used in defending against c. 645,000 crimes per year. [61] The
magnitude of this figure may be assessed by noting that it slightly exceeds the
estimated number of crimes committed or attempted by handgun-armed felons each
year, c. 581,500. [62]
Thus the empirical evidence fails to sustain the claim that handguns are
often used in crime but rarely to defeat it. Since that claim is the foundation
of the legal theory for judicial abolition of handgun manufacture via the
doctrine of strict liability the fact that defense uses approximate or actually
exceed criminal uses might seem to apply the coup de grace to that legal theory.
But factual refutation seems superfluous since the courts have not in any event
found that theory a legally sound basis for intruding into what they deem purely
legislative or political matters. [63] Yet the fact that defense uses
approximate or exceed criminal misuses emphatically does not refute the need for
legislatively imposed gun control. Controls carefully tailored to disarm felons
but not good citizens would reduce the incidence of gun misuse but not of lawful
defensive use. [63A] Moreover even a complete ban might still be advocated on
the theory that the possible benefit of reducing suicide or homicide outweighs
the certain cost of reducing the overall number of crimes thwarted by defensive
firearms use. [64]
Two other problems with the comparison given above should be noted: First, it
is impossible to tell how much the c. 645,000 crimes that handguns defend
against overlap with the c. 581,000 criminal attempts by handgun-armed felons.
Doubtless in some cases handgun-armed felon meets handgun-armed defender; but
many cases involve either felon or defender confronting an opponent who is
unarmed or armed with a knife, club, longgun or miscellaneous other weapon. [65]
Next, it is important to understand that the comparison is not of success in
either case but only of 581,000 handgun crimes attempted annually versus the
645,000 defense uses. Evidence from two sources suggests that handgun- armed
defenders succeed in repelling criminals (however armed) in 83-4% of the cases.
[70] But comparable evidence is lacking as to the rate at which handgun-armed
criminals succeed in crimes they attempt. [71]
As to the incidence of defensive gun use, an independent body of data
confirms the survey evidence of its frequency. This second data source consists
in formal or informal surveys taken among inmates of various federal and state
prisons over the past two decades. Some of these surveys are methodologically
crude and/or involve inadequate samples. [72] But since the results of all of
these surveys too are mutually consistent and supportive, it will suffice to
refer to the latest and most recent which was conducted under the auspisces of
the National Institute of Justice in state prisons across the country. [73]
While most of its questions on victim arms possession focussed on the question
of deterrent effect (see discussion infra), several did address self defense.
Responding thereto, 34% of the convicts
- said they had been "scared off, shot at, wounded or captured by an armed
victim," [quoting the actual question asked] and about two-thirds (69%) had at
least one acquaintance who had had this experience. [73]
Also suggestive of the frequency of defensive gun use were responses on two
other points: 34% of the felons said that in contemplating a crime they either
"often" or "regularly" worried that they "Might get shot at by the victim"; and
57% agreed that "Most criminals are more worried about meeting an armed victim
than they are about running into the police." [74]
Peace of Mind
To continue the religious simile with which this article began, one benefit
which must (however reluctantly) be conceded by even the most ardent atheist is
that faith may be conducive to at least a delusive peace of mind. Likewise
anti-gun claims that "those who own handguns for self-defense are engaging in
dangerous self-deception" [75] implies (however reluctantly) that at least
delusive peace of mind may be a benefit of the opposing faith. In fairness, even
ardent anti- gun advocates ought to admit the value of this in a society so
crime- ridden that they themselves proclaim that crime and the fear it creates
palpably diminishes the quality of life. [75] More neutral observers
forthrightly acknowledge that
- If people feel safer because they own a gun and in turn lead happier lives
because they feel safer and more secure, then their guns make a direct and
nontrivial contribution to their overall quality of life. [76]
Although increased peace of mind due to gun ownership may be dismissed as a
benefit only to the owners themselves and not to society as a whole it may have
wider ramifications. Two fear-related problems that have received increasing
attention in recent years are the reluctance of by-standers either to come to
the aid of victims or to bear witness against their attackers. There has been no
study of any relationship that may (or may not) exist between witnesses' or
victims' gun ownership and their likelihood of cooperating with law enforcement
authorities. But studies have linked gun ownership to Good Samaritanship: gun
owners are apparently more likely than non-owners both to feel a duty to come to
the aid of others in distress and to actually do so. [77]
Of course defensive gun ownership is a dangerous self-deception if it causes
gun owners to be injured or killed through involvement in otherwise avoidable
situations. But the evidence reviewed in the next section does not suggest that
gun ownership produces feelings of invulnerability that encourage owners to
recklessly court danger. If anything, non-owners appear less able to evaluate
the danger and the opportunities of opposing criminals, and thus more inclined
to unwise opposition, than are gun owners.
POTENTIAL COSTS OF ARMED CITIZEN RESISTANCE TO CRIME
The "success" of defensive handgun use cannot be evaluated independently of
the most obvious and immediate problem of any kind of resistance: that victims
may suffer (additional) physical injury or death who otherwise would only have
been feloniously assaulted, maimed, raped or robbed. Because of the paucity of
evidence until very recently, anti-gun arguments emphasizing these dangers have,
once again, generally had to proceed from speculation or anecdotal evidence.
[78] This lack of empirical evidence for the anti-gun viewpoint has been
obscured by a controversy which only superficially seems relevant to the dangers
of gun-armed self-defense -- largely because most of the disputants are morally
or otherwise opposed to gun ownership.
Based on national crime victim survey data, a number of scholars who happen
to be anti-gun recommend that victims eschew forcible resistance of any kind; if
an attacker cannot be "talked out" of his crime, the victim should submit in
order to avoid injury. [78A] Doubtless this submission position would excite
paroxysms of scorn from defense gun advocates like Col. Cooper [78B]. But, in
fact, its scholarly critics have not been pro-gun nor have they urged gun-armed
resistance specifically. [78C] Their criticisms involve issues of policy (that
to advise victims to submit may encourage crime [79]) and of methodological
error (e.g. that, since the data do not show time sequence, it is not clear how
often victims are injured after they resisted; they may have been harmed prior
to any resistance in that the criminal began the attack by gratuitously injuring
them which was what prompted them to resist). The latest, and probably the
definitive, analysis concludes that the "data, when interpreted carefully, do
not support any strong [general] assertions concerning the victim's safest
course of action when confronted by a robber." [80]
One criticism which has curiously been overlooked is that the submission
position is a parochial reflection of its expositors' own sexual, racial and
economic circumstances. In general, the submission position literature has
avoided any discussion of rape and invariably it treats robbery and assault as
the once-in-a-lifetime dangers which they are (at most) for salaried white
academics. It does not seem to have even occured to any submission exponent to
question whether the calculus of costs and benefits of resisting might be
different for
- an elderly Chicano whom the San Francisco Examiner reports has held onto
his grocery by outshooting fifteen armed robbers [while] nearby stores have
closed because thugs have either bankrupted them or have casually executed
their unresisting proprietors... [Or] welfare recipients whom robbers target,
knowing when their checks come and where they cash them [or] the elderly
trapped in deteriorating neighborhoods (like the Manhattan couple who in 1976
hanged themselves in despair over repeatedly losing their pension checks and
furnishings to robbers).[80A]
Regrettably, for most victims crime is not the isolated happenstance it is
for white male academics. [81] Imagine the situation of a Black shopkeeper, a
retired Marine master sergeant who has invested the life savings from
"20-years-and out" in the only store he can afford. Not coincidentally, it is
located in an area where robbery insurance is prohibitively high or unobtainable
at any price. In deciding whether to submit to robbery or resist, he and others
who live or work in such areas must weigh a factor which finds no place in the
submission position literature: that to survive they may have to establish a
reputation for not being easily victimized. [82] The submission position
literature is equally oblivious to the special factors that may have importance
for rape victims; even one rape -- much less several -- may cause catastrophic
psychological injury that may be worsened by submission, avoided by successful
resistance and mitigated even by unsuccesful resistance. [83]
By no means am I arguing that forcible resistance with guns (or without) is
optimum for crime victims in any or all circumstances. I am only only laying out
additional factors that really ought to be considered before a well-salaried
white, male intellectual presumes (as I certainly would not) to tell the kind of
people who are most often crime victims what is best for them. [83A]
At the same time it must be recognized that the considerations that underly
the submission position are irrelevant to the defensive value of guns,
notwithstanding the coincidence that that position has been championed largely
by those who happen to be anti-gun advocates. The evidence they cite does not
focus on guns nor do lessons drawn from less effective weapons seem to apply to
resistance with guns. The only extant study specific to gun-armed civilian
resisters found they suffered slightly lower rates of death or injury at the
hands of criminals (17.8%) than did police (21%). [84] These results are open to
question because the study involved only a very small sample. But confirming
evidence from an enormously larger data base is available in the national crime
victim surveys. (These, however, provide information only as to victim injury,
not death, since victims who died resisting robbers are not available to answer
survey questions.)
In fact, earlier versions of the national victim surveys were cited by the
one specifically anti-gun presentation which has tried to empirically validate
the dangers of resistance theme. [85] But the survey questions in those early
versions of the surveys lumped all resistance together without differentiating
the injury and success rates of gun-armed resisters from those of resisters who
were unarmed or armed only with less effective weapons. The more recent national
victim surveys which do so differentiate have already been cited as showing that
victims who resisted with guns were much less likely to lose their possessions
to robbers than those who resisted with any other kind of weapon. [86] As the
Table below shows, this recent data finds gun-armed resisters c. 50% less likely
to be injured as victims who did not resist at all. [87] In contrast,
knife-armed resisters were more likely to suffer injury than non-resisters and
much more likely to be injured than gun armed resisters; comparisons to other
forms of resistance are also favorable to the effectiveness of gun armed self-
defense. [87]
INSERT TABLE ABOUT HERE
Care must be taken to avoid exaggerating the importance of these findings as
support for the utility of defensive gun use. Ironically, a major factor which
might lead to exaggerating their import is a basic conceptual error in anti-gun
analyses of the utility of gun armed self- defense. Implicit in many such
anti-gun analyses has been the unexamined -- indeed unstated -- assumption that
having a gun somehow compels the victim to resist with it even in circumstances
that make it senseless and dangerous to do so. [87-1] But the whole point of a
gun (or any other precaution against emergency) is to provide an option for use
if, but only if, this is wise under the circumstances.
With this point in mind it becomes evident that the survey data on victim
injury do not support any suggestion that victims who have guns can safely
resist no matter what the circumstances. On the contrary, though guns do
maximize successful resistance, of at least equal importance in minimizing
injury is that gun owners seem mostly to eschew resistance when submission is
the wiser choice. Although the number of victims in the surveys who say they
resisted with a gun is not statistically insignificant, it is dwarfed by the
number who tried to flee or scream or resisted forcibly without a gun. [87-2]
The much higher rates of injury among victims who resisted in such ways do not
at all prove that resistance with a gun would have been safer in their
particular circumstances. Rather, the much smaller number of gun armed victims
who resisted at all suggests that gun owners may be disproportionately less
likely to resist when the circumstances for that are inauspicious. Possibly gun
owners are more likely than other victims to have considered the dangers
attendant upon resisting a criminal and are therefore more hesitant to do
so.
However absurd the concept of a thoughtful gun owner will seem to Messrs.
Grizzard, Braucher, Ellison, Wills, Clark, etc., [87A] analogy may be found in
the mid-1970s debate over the advisability of having patrol officers wear bullet
proof vests under their uniforms. Some observers feared this might actually
increase officer risk by producing a sense of invulnerability that would lead
officers to throw caution to the winds. The actual result has been the reverse:
wearing the vest seems to remind officers of how vulnerable they really are,
thereby inclining them to increased caution. [87B] By the same token, when
civilians take the momentous step of buying and actually keeping a gun for
self-protection it may provoke them to a more sober consideration of the risks
of incautious resistance. The low rate of injury to gun armed crime victims
suggests they may be more capable of evaluating the opportunities and risks of
resistance than a non-owner who, having never seriously contemplated the matter,
is suddenly confronted by a robber.
The risks and opportunities involved in the option to resist gun ownership
confers may be illustrated by considering some alternative circumstances
involving woman menaced by a rapist in her home: if she becomes aware of him as
he breaks in, the gun allows her to frighten him off or capture and hold him for
police [88]; but if her first knowledge is being awakened by the pressure of a
weapon against her throat, nothing compels her to reach for a gun. Properly
secreted it remains available for use if, for instance, believing her cowed the
rapist becomes distracted in disrobing or by a police or fire siren or some
other external event [88A]; or if it becomes clear that he intends to mutilate
or kill her regardless, so that it is rational to resist no matter how slim her
chances of success. [89] In short, a gun simply offers victims an option -- a
dangerous option to be used only with discretion and/or because throwing oneself
on the mercy of a violent attacker may be more dangerous yet. Fortunately people
who have the foresight to equip themselves with what for most victims is the
only effective means of resistance seem also to have the good judgment not to
try to use it when that would only serve to endanger them.
A Note on self defense and the Issue of Massacres In July, 1984 an unemployed
and apparently deranged security guard killed 21 customers and employees at a
San Ysidro California MacDonalds Hamburger outlet. [90] In August, 1986 a
similar massacre in which 15 died was perpetrated in an Oklahoma Post Office by
a recently discharged postal worker using guns he had received as a National
Guard marskmanship instructor. [91] Both of the perpetrators remained on the
scene to be killed, eschewing any opportunity to escape before the police
arrived.
It is ironic that these and similar tragedies of the past three decades have
been seen as arguing for, rather than against, gun bans. [92] Massacre presents
a situation in which the value of defensive firearm use is at least arguable,
while standard anti-gun arguments have no force at all: The most important
argument against forcible resistance is that it may cause a criminal to kill a
victim whom he would otherwise only rob or rape. Obviously that argument has no
application to a situation in which a deranged killer opens fire without
provocation or making any demand for his victims to satisfy. Also inapplicable
by its own terms is the argument that even though a gun ban may disarm the
victim it may also disarm the attacker. Basic to that argument is the
proposition that in acquaintance or domestic homicide situations killers often
act out of momentary rage, not out of a fixed intent to kill. From this premise
it follows that such killings might not occur but for the immediate access to
firearms. [93]
Realistic gun control advocates recognize the impossibility of disarming the
killer who really wants to kill and wants a gun for that purpose. They thus
implicitly, and often explicitly, concede that gun control measures can be of
little use against killers so highly motivated for personal or political reasons
as to undertake massacres which are substantially likely to result in their own
deaths. [94] A contrasting policy alternative for dealing with this special
problem is exemplified by an incident which occured in a Jerusalem cafe four
months before the San Ysidro MacDonalds massacre: three terrorists who attempted
to machine-gun the crowd were able to kill only 1 victim before being shot down
by handgun-armed Israelis. When presented to the press the next day the
surviving terrorist bitterly complained that his group had not realized that
Isreali civilians were armed. The terrorists had planned to machine-gun a
succession of crowd spots, believing that they would be able to escape before
the police or army could arrive to deal with them. [95]
In sum, anti-gun policies not only offer no solution for the massacre
situation but are detrimental in precluding whatever chance the victims might
have to protect themselves in the crucial time it will take the police to arrive
on the scene. [96] Because terrorism is its most pressing criminal justice
problem, Israel maximizes the presence of armed citizens by firearms training
and encouraging gun ownership and carrying by almost the entire populace (Jews
of both sexes and for the Druze and other pro-Israeli Arabs). [97] The
advisability of such measures in a country in which military training is not
universal even for males presents quite a different question - which does not
necessarily merit even examination since American homicide is not primarily a
matter of massacres. [97A] Melodramatic as they were, the MacDonalds and Post
Office massacres combined constituted only a fraction of 1% of the criminal
homicide totals for those years. The massacre issue is thus a "red herring"; and
the use made of it by anti-gun advocates is at once ironic and evidence of the
simple-minded and/or unscrupulous debate which is, unfortunately, no less
characteristic of them than of the gun lobby. [98]
DETERRENCE
To reiterate, as used herein deterrence refers not to the actual use of a gun
in repelling an attempted crime (defense use) but to the phenomenon of crime not
even being attempted because of the potential criminal's fear of confronting an
armed civilian. There are several kinds of such deterrence as Prof. Gary Green
has noted in emphasizing the need to distinguish between them: in "displacement"
the effect when some victims (or neighborhoods or communities) are perceived as
well armed is only the redirection of the same crime against others; in sharp
contrast are both "total deterrence", in which criminals are deterred from crime
altogether, and "confrontation deterrence", in which they are deterred
altogether from crimes like rape or robbery which involve confronting a victim.
[99]
Ignoring the vital distinction between displacement and total or
confrontation deterrence has allowed pro-gun advocates to present the evidence
on deterrence as less ambiguous and equivocal than it really is. Blythely
assuming that deterring crimes against victims perceived to be well armed
reduces the total quantum of crime -- rather than just foisting it off on other
victims -- extreme pro-gun advocates support arming the populace as a deterrent
to crime. Thus when Ford Administration Attorney General Edward H. Levi proposed
forbidding guns in high crime areas, Ronald Reagan (then a private citizen)
commented in an article published in a gun journal:
- Mightn't it be better in those areas of high crime to arm the homeowner
and the shopkeeper, teach him how to use his weapons and put the word out to
the underworld that it is no longer totally safe to rob and murder?... One
wonders indeed if the rising crime rate isn't due as much as anything to the
criminal's instinctive knowledge that the average victim no longer has any
means of self-protection... No one knows how many crimes are committed because
the criminal knows he has a soft touch. No one knows how many stores have been
let alone because the criminals knew it [sic] was guarded by a man with a gun
or manned by a proprietor who knew how to use a gun. [100]
Local "experiments" in deterrence through publicizing gun
ownership--
As pro-gun advocates like former NRA chief lobbyist Neal Knox are quick to
note, experiments involving the deterrent effect of an armed victim population
seem to have been very successful: [101]
- in 1966 there were a series of brutal rapes in Orlando, Florida which
panicked the women of the city into buying firearms for defense. Fearing a
rash of accidental shootings, the local news- paper co-sponsored a firearms
training class conducted by the police department; in the next few months some
6,000 [sic -- the actual number was c. 3,000] women were trained in firearms
safety and through the extensively publicized program. The results were
remarkable... [In 1967] Orlando was the only city in the U.S. of more than
100,000 population to show a decrease in crime.
Mr. Knox's article continues:
- An equally startling example of the crime-deterrent value of
well-publicized gun ownership occured in 1967 in Highland Park, Michigan, a
Detroit suburb. Having read of the Orlando and similar firearms training
programs, Police Chief Bill Stephens conducted a firearms training program for
retail merchants who were being plagued by an unprecedented number of armed
robberies... [This was denounced by the anti-gun Detroit Police Commissioner]
resulting in headlines in Detroit newspapers. Four months after the program
began [Chief Stephens reported] that armed robbery of retail stores had been
averaging two every three days immediately prior to the announcement of the
training program; but from the day the newspapers carried the story, there had
been not a single retail store robbery in the city -- for a third of a year!
- [In Detroit itself a grocers' association sponsored such classes which
were publicized both because of the Police Commissioner's criticism and
because] in the following few months seven armed robbers were killed by store
owners -- and Detroit grocery store robberies dropped by almost 90%. [103]
In fairness, pro-gun advocates have some excuse for missing this point since
their opponents have generally, though unintentionally, diverted attention from
it. Anti-gun works like HOW WELL DOES THE HANDGUN PROTECT YOU AND YOUR FAMILY
[105A] invariably frame the issue as whether gun ownership actually protects the
individual family. By focussing on that pro-gun advocates have been able to
overlook the inconvenient reality that, though it clearly does serve the
interest of the individual gun owning family to displace criminal attackers onto
the unarmed, no larger social utility accrues if such attacks are not thereby
decreased overall.
Indeed, if displacement were the only effect it could be argued that
deterrence is actually socially deleterious. Assume for the sake of discussion
that programs that dramatize that women in a particular area are well armed only
displace rape to some other area where it is less likely that the rapist will
confront an armed victim. Of course those who appraise probabilities more
realistically than the gun lobby will conclude that many times even armed
victims will not be able to defeat a criminal. [106] But from the perspective of
overall social benefit the important point is that the likelihood of rape being
repelled is enormously greater if the victim is armed than if she is a helpless
victim -- a fortiori even more so the chances that the rapist will be
apprehended or killed (thereby disabling him from further rape) or frightened
into eschewing rape in the future. [107] So deterrence would be socially
counter-productive if all it caused were displacement, thereby actually
diminishing the defense-use benefits that would otherrwise accrue to society
from civilian gun ownership.
Fortunately the deterrent effect of civilian arms possession is not limited
to displacement. As Prof. Green recognizes, realistically the great majority of
rapists are not, when deterred from striking at one place, going to commit at
least as many rapes elsewhere. Even as to rapists who pre-plan their crimes, the
reduction in incidence will be not insubstantial since planning for a new area
(i.e., out of the area with which the criminal is most familiar) creates both
real and psychological problems. [108] Of course the incidence of rapes (or
other crimes) committed opportunistically may especially be reduced when a
criminal becomes frightened of the victims likely to be found in his regular
haunts.
At the same time it must be recognized that displacment effects are not
unique to the deterrent value of civilian gun possession; they apply, and must
be taken into account in appriasing, any kind of crime deterrence program. For
instance, a drastic increase in numbers of uniformed police assigned to ride the
New York subways at night was followed by robbery reduction during those hours
-- but robbery then increased during daytime subway operations. Nevertheless
since the daytime increase was far less than the nighttime decrease the program
must be accounted a net success. [109] Thus the possibility of displacement does
not refute the value of programs designed to deter crime, including publicizing
victim armament. The point is only that careful study, with displacement being
taken into consideration, is what is needed if the existence and extent of such
net gain is to be accurately appraised.
On the importance of deterring confrontation criminals into
non-confrontation crimes
As suggested above, even as to rape it may reasonably be assumed the
deterrent effect of a highly publicized firearms training program for potential
victims may produce significant net reduction overall. As to other kinds of
crimes the deterrent effect may be much greater. The difference is that because
for rape there is no non-confrontation alternative, the deterrent on a rapist
must be total. In contrast, to reduce the incidence of a crime like robbery the
deterrent need only frighten robbers into non-confrontation alternatives such as
dealing drugs, stealing cars, burglarizing unoccupied premises, forgery etc.
Since these are also serious felonies, such deterrence is not an unalloyed
benefit as Prof. Green has pointed out. [109A] But since deterring confrontation
crime into non-confrontation crime radically decreases likelihood of victim
death or injury, its social benefit is very great.
This point has unaccountably been missed by those who have made the one
anti-gun argument that remains viable in light of present evidence about the
defensive value of arms possession. A leit motif thoughout their analyses has
been that guns are rarely used against burglars because burglars take care to
strike only when premises are unoccupied. [110] It appears that a major reason
for that care is fear of meeting an armed householder. [111] If so, civilian
arms possession palpably and substantially benefits burglary victims by
minimizing their risk of injury or death in confrontations with burglars. It is
only because few burglaries occur when premises are occupied that physical
injury to victims is comparatively rare in burglary. Victim surveys show injury
to be quite frequent in the 12.7% of burglaries that involve occupied premises.
[112] The deterrent effect of civilian arms possession can be largely credited
for the far lower rate of victim injury or death in burglaries than in robberies
which are, by definition, confrontation offenses. [113]
Thus programs that promote civilian arms possession palpably serve the public
good if the publicity they generate deters robbers into non- confrontational
burglary. It is worth noting that such non- confrontantion deterrence
constitutes a reversal of Prof. Green's observation that displacement deterrence
benefits only gun owners and not society. In this instance civilian arms
possession aids society but not gun owners in particular for rarely do burglars
know the gun owners' homes from those of non-owners (nor, if the burglar is
really careful to strike when no one is home to shoot, would the distinction
matter to him). So any reduction in victim injury or death consequent upon this
care benefits potential victims in general but not gun owners more than others.
[114]
Difficulties and complexities of deterrent effects Though the evidence so far
reviewed provides relatively strong support for the deterrent effect of civilian
arms possession in the abstract, as to formulating concrete policy it raises
almost as many questions as it resolves. Dramatic decreases in confrontation
crime have followed in the wake of local programs dramatizing victim arms
possession. [114A] But even leaving aside the issue of displacement, two
questions suggest themselves: would such programs be legal and practicable if
tried on a regional, state or anything beyond the purely local level; and, even
if such programs did work in broader application, does their deterrent effect
continue over time or is it merely transitory? [115]
Related to, but transcending, these questions is the probative significance
of such programs for the broader deterrent implications of an armed civilian
population. The gun lobby cites the apparently dramatic effects of the Orlando
and other local programs as proving that widespread gun ownership must reduce
violent crime. Now at least unless one is a priori opposed to guns it will be
intuitively evident that to grow up in an area where criminals are frequently
shot by victims would at least tend to disincline people to confrontation
offenses. But this intuition is only remotely supported by such local program
results as the 90% reduction in Detroit grocery robberies when gun training for
grocers led to the well publicized shootings of 7 armed robbers. [116] Perhaps
hearing of 7 such deaths over a few weeks time has a shock effect on a
fellow-robber that far exceeds the general deterrent effect of having heard of
25-30 such deaths over the entire period in which he grew up. Conversely,
perhaps such a shock effect is only temporary; perhaps having grown up hearing
of two or three such deaths each year would produce a greater deterrent effect
on the prospective criminal's psyche over the long run. But "perhapses" are not
evidence; or, rather, they are evidence of the numerous questions that remain
after such evidence as exists is evaluated.
Moreover in evaluating these and other questions it must be remembered that a
deterrent does not constitute an absolute bar to crime but only a disincentive,
something which counters tendencies and creates disinclination. In an area where
opportunities for non- confrontation crime are low, the incentive to rob might
well outweigh the aversive tendency or disinclination created even for criminals
who have grown up routinely hearing of incidents of robbers being killed by
their victims. Doubtless widely publicized firearms training for victims (or a
series of shootings of criminals by victims) might dramatically reduce the
number of robberies for some period of time. But perhaps this result would
reflect only an immediate shock effect without lasting impact on robbery
rates.
Nor can the evidence as to burglary be heedlessly generalized to suggest that
civilian arms possession will have comparable deterrent effects on more
dangerous kinds of crime and criminals. In itself the fact that almost 90% of
home burglaries occur when the premises are unoccupied suggests that burglars
generally want to avoid confronting armed householders. This is confirmed from
statements by criminals themselves, including the responses to the National
Institute of Justice felon survey. [117] But, again, the deterrent can not be
evaluated independent of the incentive. Compare the two in relation to robbing
liquor stores versus burglarizing occupied homes: In each case the deterrent
(being shot by the victim) is the same yet the robbers' incentive to
confrontation is immensely greater. To offset the robbers' risk of getting shot
there is the incentive of a substantial cash take. But to off-set the risk a
burglar takes by not eschewing occupied premises there is only the prospect of
adding to the goods he steals from the home the marginal amount of cash he may
get from the person of a householder he confronts. [118] This very real
difference in the incentives to confrontations in the two crimes clearly appears
in the responses to different questions in the National Institute of Justice
felon survey: 74% of the inmates agreed "One reason burglars avoid houses when
people are home is that they fear being shot during the crime", but only 58%
agreed that "A store owner who is known to keep a gun on the premises is not
going to get robbed very often." [119]
These and other results of the felon survey do significantly support (albeit
with significant reservations) the intuition that the phenomenon of criminals
being repelled by armed victims does deter confrontation crime. In addition to
the results just noted, 56% of the felons agreed that "A criminal is not going
to mess around with a victim he knows is armed with a gun" and 57% that "Most
criminals are more worried about meeting an armed victim than they are about
running into the police." Over 80% of the felons felt that a criminal should
always try to determine whether his victim was armed, while 39% said they
personally had aborted at least one crime because of belief that the intended
victim was armed and 8% said they had done so "many" times. [120] "Beyond all
doubt, criminals clearly worry about confronting an armed victim" is the summary
given by the National Institute of Justice analysts. [121] As they recognize,
however, to "worry" is not the same as to be deterred from the activity which
causes the worry -although worry may deter even an violent criminal into
committing markedly less confrontation crime than he would in its absence. And a
risk that worries even hard core violent criminals whose courage is (as we shall
see) likely to be fortified by potent combinations of alcohol and illegal drugs,
may completely deter the less violently inclined or less experienced or less
reckless criminal. Overall the results of the felon survey suggest the deterrent
effect of victim armament is a substantial reason why some felons specialize in
non-confrontation crime only and eschew the greater immediate rewards of
confrontation crime altogether.
Yet the results are both more mixed and more complex than the gun lobby would
like to admit. [122] About 40% of the felons claimed that in planning a crime
they never even considered the possibility of being shot by a victim -- and
almost one-quarter of them said they actually found victim armament an
incentive, "an exciting challenge." [123] Some of this can be dismissed as macho
posturing. Felons may be able to be more candid in describing the fears of
criminals in the abstract than in describing their own. But it must also be
considered that a subset of the criminal population which is disproportionately
significant because murders and accidental fatalities are so heavily
concentrated among them are characterized by a signal indifference to human
life, including their own. [124] There is no necessary inconsistency between the
attitudes of this subset and indifference -or even attraction -- to armed
victims.
Moreover, another and larger subset, the "violent predators", [125] are
characterized by very high rates of substance abuse (which is true of the most
murderous subset as well). Referring to the sub- groups they denominated
respectively as handgun or shotgun predators, the National Institue of Justice
analysts described them as "criminal opportunists ... omnibus felons" whose days
out of prison are devoted to indiscriminate criminality -- "more or less any
crime they had the opportunity to commit." [130] Just as such omnivorousness
violates the stereotype that criminals normally stick to some specialty like
robbery, burglary or forgery, so does the omnivorousness of their substance
abuse violate stereotypes of the simple heroin or cocaine or marijuana user.
Predators are likely not only to alternate these drugs with liquor, barbituates
etc., etc., but to combine them in various fashions. With their spirits
fortified with liquor, cocaine, PCP etc., singly or in combination, the violent
predators may be relatively indifferent to the danger of confronting an armed
victim. [131] But even if they are not, addicts' desperation to finance their
drug habits may make them willing to court that danger.
Clearly worry about being shot by an armed victim did not deter many of the
felons in this sample from a life of confrontation crime. Such worries may deter
other criminals into non-confrontation crime and it may reduce the rate at which
even violent predators engage in confrontation crimes. But the number of violent
offenses which are nevertheless attempted prove that many criminals on many
occasions can overcome their fears of the deterrent presented both by an armed
citizenry and by the police and the prospect of punishment by the courts.
CONCLUSION
This article began with the proposition that both pro- and anti- gun
positions on the utility of guns against crime had been arrived at by faith in
the period before the existence of credible empirical evidence on the issues.
Having examined the evidence that has become available in the last decade it
must be concluded that parts of each faith have been sustained:
As to actual defensive handgun uses, the evidence from surveys both of
civilians and of felons is that they are much more frequent than has previously
been realized. It may tentatively be concluded that handguns are used as or more
often to prevent the commission of crimes than by felons attempting them. This
should not be understood as suggesting that the decision to resist a felon can
be made lightly or that their handguns automatically insulate resisters from
injury. The unique defensive value of a handgun is not the only cause for
comparatively low rates of injury among gun-armed resisters; as or more
important is the wisdom not to resist in circumstances in which this is unlikely
to succeed.
As to the gun lobby's vaunted deterrent effect of gun ownership the evidence
is even more equivocal. In general (though not without equivocation) it does
support the common sense intuition that the average criminal has no more desire
to face an armed citizen than the average citizen has to face an armed criminal.
Widespread defensive gun ownership benefits society as a whole by deterring
burglars into making efforts to avoid occupied premises; and by deterring from
confrontation offenses altogether an unknown proportion of criminals who might
otherwise be attracted by the immediate profitability of robbery into committing
at least a few of them. Even when criminals are not so deterred, widespread gun
ownership may frighten them into reducing the overall number of such offenses
they commit; and it does frighten them into abandoning some specific offenses --
particularly in areas where special local programs have dramatized the
likelihood of victim arms possession. Yet it must also be noted that the
possibility that gun ownership reduces the activity level of confrontation
offenders is only an unsubstantiated speculation; gun lobby propaganda has
exaggerated the deterrent effect of gun ownership by not discounting for
displacement effects that represent no net gain in overall crime reduction.
Finally some caveats may be offered on the limited import of the evidence I
have reviewed for issues of firearms regulation: clearly this evidence disposes
of the claim that handguns are so lacking in social utility that courts should,
in effect, ban their sale to the general public under the doctrine of liability
without fault. This evidence likewise cuts strongly against severe statutory
restrictions based on the belief that handgun ownership offers few social
benefits to offset the harms associated with it. But even if strict liability
for guns were factually supportable, it is very evident that the courts are
unwilling to accept it as a matter of law. [136] Moreover, even if handguns
offered no benefits whatever, neither does banning them -- except as part of a
policy of outlawing and confiscating guns of all kinds. [137]
What the evidence on crime reductive utility of firearms most definitely does
not do is undercut the case for controls tailored to deny firearms of all kinds
to felons, juveniles and the mentally impaired. Indeed, Professors Kleck and
Bordua, the criminologists principally responsible for documenting that utility,
remain strongly supportive of such controls (if carefully tailored not to
prevent handgun ownership among the responsible adult population). [138]
Moreover it is still possible to argue for going beyond control to the
prohibition and confiscation of (all kinds of) firearms if it can realistically
be posited that the net gain in reducing suicide, gun accident and certain kinds
of homicide might outweigh the reductive effect of civilian firearms ownership
on crime.
References
Return to Technical Data Table of
Contents
Return to Second Thoughts Home
Page